Loading ...
Global Do...
News & Politics
6
0
Try Now
Log In
Pricing
Doomsday argument World population from 10,000 BC to AD 2000 The Doomsday argument (DA) is a probab- ilistic argument that claims to predict the fu- ture lifetime of the human species given only an estimate of the total number of humans born so far. Simply put, it says that suppos- ing the humans alive today are in a random place in the whole human history timeline, chances are we are about halfway through it. It was first proposed in an explicit way by the astrophysicist Brandon Carter in 1983,[1] from which it is sometimes called the Carter catastrophe; the argument was sub- sequently championed by the philosopher John A. Leslie and has since been independ- ently discovered by J. Richard Gott[2] and Holger Bech Nielsen.[3] Similar principles of eschatology were proposed earlier by Heinz von Foerster, among others. Denoting by N the total number of humans who were ever or will ever be born, the Co- pernican principle suggests that we are equally likely (along with the other N − 1 hu- mans) to find ourselves at any position n, so we assume that our fractional position f = n/N is uniformly distributed on the inter- val (0, 1] prior to learning our absolute position. Let us further assume that our fractional position f is uniformly distributed on (0, 1] even after we learn of our absolute position n. (This is equivalent to the assumption that we have no prior information about the total number of humans, N.) That is, for example, there is 95% chance that f is in the interval (0.05, 1], that is f > 0.05. In other words we could assume that we could be 95% certain that we would be within the last 95% of all the humans ever to be born. If we know our absolute position n, this implies an upper bound for N obtained by rearranging n/N > 0.05 to give N < 20n. If we take that 60 billion humans have been born so far (Leslie’s figure), then we can estimate that there is a 95% chance that the total number of humans N will be less than 20 × 60 billion = 1.2 trillion. Assuming that the world population stabilizes at 10 bil- lion and a life expectancy of 80 years, it can be estimated that the remaining 1140 billion humans will be born in 9120 years. Depend- ing on the projection of world population in the forthcoming centuries, estimates may vary, but the main point of the argument is that it is unlikely that more than 1.2 trillion humans will ever live. Aspects Remarks • The step that converts N into an extinction time depends upon a finite human lifespan. If immortality becomes common, and the birth rate drops to zero, N will never be reached.[4] • The total number of humans born so far may depend on one’s definition of "human". • A precise formulation of the Doomsday Argument requires the Bayesian interpretation of probability, which is widely, if not universally, accepted. • Even among Bayesians some of the assumptions of the argument’s logic would not be acceptable; for instance, the fact that it is applied to a temporal phenomenon (how long something lasts) means that N’s distribution simultaneously represents an "aleatory probability" (as a future event), and an "epistemic probability" (as a decided value about which we are uncertain). • The U(0,1] f distribution is derived from two choices, which whilst being the default are also arbitrary: • The principle of indifference, so that it is as likely for any other randomly selected person to be born after you as before you. From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Doomsday argument 1 • The assumption of no ’prior’ knowledge on the distribution of N. Simplification: two possible total number of humans Assume for simplicity that the total number of humans who will ever be born is 60 billion (N1), or 6,000 billion (N2).[5] If there is no prior knowledge of the position that a cur- rently living individual, X, has in the history of humanity, we may instead compute how many humans were born before X, and arrive at (say) 59,854,795,447, which would roughly place X amongst the first 60 billion humans who have ever lived. Now, if we assume that the number of hu- mans who will ever be born equals N1, the probability that X is amongst the first 60 bil- lion humans who have ever lived is of course 100%. However, if the number of humans who will ever be born equals N2, then the probability that X is amongst the first 60 bil- lion humans who have ever lived is only 1%. Since X is in fact amongst the first 60 billion humans who have ever lived, this means that the total number of humans who will ever be born is more likely to be much closer to 60 billion than to 6,000 billion. In essence the DA therefore suggests that human extinction is more likely to occur sooner rather than later. It is possible to sum the probabilities for each value of N and therefore to compute a statistical ’confidence limit’ on N. For ex- ample, taking the numbers above, it is 99% certain that N is smaller than 6,000 billion. What the argument is not The Doomsday argument (DA) does not say that humanity cannot or will not exist indefin- itely. It does not put any upper limit on the number of humans that will ever exist, nor provide a date for when humanity will be- come extinct. An abbreviated form of the argument does make these claims, by confusing probability with certainty. However, the actual DA’s con- clusion is: There is a 95% chance of extinction within 9120 years. The DA gives a 5% chance that some humans will still be alive in about the year 11125. (These dates are based on the assumptions above; the precise numbers vary among spe- cific Doomsday arguments.) Variations This argument has generated a lively philo- sophical debate, and no consensus has yet emerged on its solution. The variants de- scribed below produce the DA by separate derivations. Gott’s formulation: ’vague prior’ total population Gott specifically proposes the functional form for the prior distribution of the number of people who will ever be born (N). Gott’s DA used the vague prior distribution: . where • P(N) is the probability prior to discovering n, the total number of humans who have yet been born. • The constant, k, is chosen to normalize the sum of P(N). The value chosen isn’t important here, just the functional form (this is an improper prior, so no value of k gives a valid distribution, but Bayesian inference is still possible using it.) Since Gott specifies the prior distribution of total humans, P(N), Bayes’s theorem and the principle of indifference alone give us P(N|n), the probability of N humans being born if n is a random draw from N: This is Bayes’s theorem for the posterior probability of total population exactly N, con- ditioned on current population exactly n. Now, using the indifference principle: . The unconditioned n distribution of the cur- rent population is identical to the vague prior N probability density function,[6] so: , From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Doomsday argument 2 giving P (N | n) for each specific N (through a substitution into the posterior probability equation): . The easiest way to produce the doomsday es- timate with a given confidence (say 95%) is to pretend that N is a continuous variable (since it is very large) and integrate over the probability density from N = n to N = Z. (This will give a function for the probability that N ≤ Z): Defining Z = 20n gives: . This is the simplest Bayesian derivation of the Doomsday Argument: The chance that the total number of humans that will ever be born (N) is greater than twenty times the total that have been is below 5% The use of a vague prior distribution seems well-motivated as it assumes as little know- ledge as possible about N, given that any par- ticular function must be chosen. It is equival- ent to the assumption that the probability density of one’s fractional position remains uniformly distributed even after learning of one’s absolute position (n). Gott’s ’reference class’ in his original 1993 paper was not the number of births, but the number of years ’humans’ had existed as a species, which he put at 200,000. Also, Gott tried to give a 95% confidence interval between a minimum survival time and a max- imum. Because of the 2.5% chance that he gives to underestimating the minimum he has only a 2.5% chance of overestimating the maximum. This equates to 97.5% confidence that extinction occurs before the upper boundary of his confidence interval. 97.5% is one chance in forty, which can be used in the integral above with Z = 40n, and n = 200,000 years: This is how Gott produces a 97.5% confid- ence of extinction within N ≤ 8,000,000 years. The number he quoted was the likely time remaining, N − n = 7.8 million years. This was much higher than the temporal con- fidence bound produced by counting births, because it applied the principle of indiffer- ence to time. (Producing different estimates by sampling different parameters in the same hypothesis is Bertrand’s paradox.) His choice of 95% confidence bounds (rather than 80% or 99.9%, say) matched the scientifically accepted limit of statistical sig- nificance for hypothesis rejection. Therefore, he argued that the hypothesis: “humanity will cease to exist before 5,100 years or thrive beyond 7.8 million years” can be rejected. Leslie’s argument differs from Gott’s ver- sion in that he does not assume a vague prior probability distribution for N. Instead he ar- gues that the force of the Doomsday Argu- ment resides purely in the increased probab- ility of an early Doomsday once you take into account your birth position, regardless of your prior probability distribution for N. He calls this the probability shift. Heinz von Foerster argued that human- ity’s abilities to construct societies, civiliza- tions and technologies do not result in self in- hibition. Rather, societies’ success varies dir- ectly with population size. Von Foerster found that this model fit some 25 data points from the birth of Jesus to 1958, with only 7% of the variance left unexplained. Several follow-up letters (1961, 1962, …) were pub- lished in Science showing that von Foerster’s equation was still on track. The data contin- ued to fit up until 1973. The most remarkable thing about von Foerster’s model was it pre- dicted that the human population would reach infinity or a mathematical singularity, on Friday, November 13, 2026. In fact, von Foerster did not imply that the world popula- tion on that day could actually become infin- ite. The real implication was that the world population growth pattern followed for many centuries prior to 1960 was about to come to an end and be transformed into a radically different pattern. Note that this prediction began to be fulfilled just in a few years after the "Doomsday" was published.[7] Reference classes One of the major areas of Doomsday Argu- ment debate is the reference class from From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Doomsday argument 3 which n is drawn, and of which N is the ulti- mate size. The ’standard’ Doomsday Argu- ment hypothesis doesn’t spend very much time on this point, and simply says that the reference class is the number of ’humans’. Given that you are human, the Copernican principle could be applied to ask if you were born unusually early, but the grouping of ’hu- man’ has been widely challenged on practical and philosophical grounds. Nick Bostrom has argued that consciousness is (part of) the dis- criminator between what is in and what is out of the reference class, and that extrater- restrial intelligences might affect the calcula- tion dramatically. The following sub-sections relate to differ- ent suggested reference classes, each of which has had the standard Doomsday Argu- ment applied to it. Sampling only WMD-era humans The Doomsday clock shows the expected time to nuclear doomsday by the judgment of an expert board, rather than a Bayesian model. If the twelve hours of the clock symbolize the lifespan of the human species, its current time of 11:55 implies that we are among the last 1% of people who will ever be born (i.e. that n > 0.99N). J. Richard Gott’s temporal version of the Doomsday argument (DA) would require very strong prior evidence to overcome the improbability of being born in such a special time. If the clock’s doomsday estimate is correct, there is less than 1 chance in 100 of seeing it show such a late time in human history, if observed at a random time within that history. The scientists’ warning can be reconciled with the DA, however: The Doomsday clock specifically estimates the proximity of atomic self-destruction - which has only been pos- sible for sixty years.[8] If doomsday requires nuclear weaponry then the Doomsday Argu- ment ’reference class’ is: people contempor- aneous with nuclear weapons. In this model, the number of people living through, or born after Hiroshima is n, and the number of people who ever will is N. Applying Gott’s DA to these variable definitions gives a 50% chance of doomsday within 50 years. In this model, the clock’s hands are so close to midnight because a condition of doomsday is living post-1945, a condition which applies now but not to the earlier 11 hours and 53 minutes of the clock’s metaphorical human ’day’. If your life is randomly selected from all lives lived under the shadow of the bomb, this simple model gives a 95% chance of dooms- day within 1000 years. The scientists’ recent use of moving the clock forward to warn of the dangers posed by global warming muddles this reasoning, however. SSSA: Sampling from observer- moments Nick Bostrom, considering observation selec- tion effects, has produced a Self-Sampling Assumption (SSA): "that you should think of yourself as if you were a random observer from a suitable reference class". If the ’refer- ence class’ is the set of humans to ever be born, this gives N < 20n with 95% confidence (the standard Doomsday argument). However, he has refined this idea to apply to observer-moments rather than just observ- ers. He has formalized this ([2] as: The Strong Self-Sampling Assumption (SSSA): Each observer-moment should reason as if it were randomly selected from the class of all observer-moments in its reference class. If the minute in which you read this article is randomly selected from every minute in every human’s lifespan then (with 95% con- fidence) this event has occurred after the first 5% of human observer-moments. If fu- ture mean lifespan is twice historic, this im- plies 95% confidence that N < 10n (the aver- age future human will account for twice the observer-moments of the average historic hu- man). Therefore, the 95th percentile extinction-time estimate in this version is 4560 years. Rebuttals We are in the earliest 5%, a priori If you agree with the statistical methods, still disagreeing with the Doomsday argument (DA) implies that: From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Doomsday argument 4 1. We within the first 5% of humans to be born. 2. This is purely a coincidence. Therefore, these rebuttals try to give reasons for believing that we are some of the earliest humans. For instance, you are member 50,000 in a collaborative project, the Doomsday Argu- ment implies a 95% chance that there will never be more than a million members of that project. This can be refuted if your other characteristics are typical of the early adop- ter. The mainstream of potential users will prefer to be involved when the project is nearly complete. If you enjoy the project’s in- completeness, we already know that you are unusual, prior to the discovery of your early involvement. If you have measurable attributes that set you apart from the typical long run user, the project DA can be refuted based on the fact that you would expect to be within the first 5% of members, a priori. The analogy to the total-human-population form of the argument is: Confidence in a prediction of the distribu- tion of human characteristics that places modern & historic humans outside the main- stream, implies that we already know, before examining n that it is likely to be very early in N. For example, if you are certain that 99% of humans who will ever live will be cyborgs, but you are not a cyborg, you could be equally certain that at least one hundred times as many people remain to be born as have been. Robin Hanson’s paper sums up these criti- cisms of the DA: "All else is not equal; we have good reasons for thinking we are not randomly selected humans from all who will ever live." Drawbacks of this rebuttal: 1. The question of how the confident prediction is derived. We need an uncannily prescient picture of humanity’s statistical distribution through all time, before we can pronounce ourselves extreme members of that population. (In contrast, project pioneers have clearly distinct psychology from the mainstream.) 2. If the majority of humans have characteristics we do not share, some would argue that this is equivalent to the Doomsday argument, since people like us will become extinct. (Friedrich Nietzsche outlines this pseudoextinction point of view in Also sprach Zarathustra.) Critique: Human extinction is distant, a posteriori The a posteriori observation that extinction level events are rare could be offered as evid- ence that the DA’s predictions are implaus- ible; typically, extinctions of a dominant spe- cies happens less often than once in a million years. Therefore, it is argued that Human ex- tinction is unlikely within the next ten millen- nia. (Another probabilistic argument, draw- ing a different conclusion from the DA.) In Bayesian terms, this response to the DA says that our knowledge of history (or ability to prevent disaster) produces a prior margin- al for N with a minimum value in the trillions. If N is distributed uniformly from 1012 to 1013, for example, then the probability of N < 1,200 billion inferred from n = 60 billion will be extremely small. This is an equally impec- cable Bayesian calculation, rejecting the Co- pernican principle on the grounds that we must be ’special observers’ since there is no likely mechanism for humanity to go extinct within the next hundred thousand years. This response is accused of overlooking the technological threats to humanity’s sur- vival, to which earlier life was not subject, and is specifically rejected by most of the DA’s academic critics (arguably excepting Robin Hanson). In fact, many futurologists believe the em- pirical situation is worse than Gott’s DA es- timate. For instance, Sir Martin Rees be- lieves that the technological dangers give an estimated human survival duration of ninety- five years (with 50% confidence.) Earlier prophets made similar predictions and were ’proven’ wrong (e.g. on surviving the nuclear arms race). It is possible that their estimates were accurate, and that their common image as alarmists is a survivorship bias. The prior N distribution may make n very uninformative Robin Hanson argues that N’s prior may be exponentially distributed: From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Doomsday argument 5 Here, c and q are constants. If q is large, then our 95% confidence upper bound is on the uniform draw, not the exponential value of N. The best way to compare this with Gott’s Bayesian argument is to flatten the distribu- tion from the vague prior by having the prob- ability fall off more slowly with N (that in- verse proportionally). This corresponds to the idea that humanity’s growth may be exponen- tial in time with doomsday having a vague prior pdf in time. This would mean than N, the last birth, would have a distribution look- ing like the following: This prior N distribution is all that is required (with the principle of indifference) to produce the inference of N from n, and this is done in an identical way to the standard case, as de- scribed by Gott (equivalent to α = 1 in this distribution): Substituting into the posterior probability equation): Integrating the probability of any N above xn: For example, if x = 20, and α = 0.5, this becomes: Therefore, with this prior, the chance of a trillion births is well over 20%, rather than the 5% chance given by the standard DA. If α is reduced further by assuming a flatter prior N distribution, then the limits on N given by n become weaker. An α of one reproduces Gott’s calculation with a birth reference class, and α around 0.5 could approximate his temporal confidence interval calculation (if the population were expanding exponen- tially). As (gets smaller) n becomes less and less informative about N. In the limit this distribution approaches an (unbounded) uniform distribution, where all values of N are equally likely. This is Page et al.’s "Assumption 3", which they find few reas- ons to reject, a priori. (Although all distribu- tions with are improper priors, this applies to Gott’s vague-prior distribution also, and they can all be converted to pro- duce proper integrals by postulating a finite upper population limit.) Since the probability of reaching a population of size 2N is usually thought of as the chance of reaching N multi- plied by the survival probability from N to 2N it seems that Pr(N) must be a monotonically decreasing function of N, but this doesn’t ne- cessarily require an inverse proportionality. A prior distribution with a very low α para- meter makes the DA’s ability to constrain the ultimate size of humanity very weak. Infinite Expectation Another objection to the Doomsday Argument is that the expected total human population is actually infinite. The calculation is as follows: The total human population N = n/f, where n is the human population to date and f is our fractional position in the total. We assume that f is uniformly distributed on (0,1]. The expectation of N is This infinite expectation shows that, under the framework of the DA, humanity still has some chance of surviving an arbitrarily long time. For a similar example of counterintuitive infinite expectations, see the St. Petersburg paradox. SIA: The possibility of not exist- ing at all One objection is that the possibility of you ex- isting at all depends on how many humans will ever exist (N). If this is a high number, then the possibility of you existing is higher than if only a few humans will ever exist. Since you do indeed exist, this is evidence that the number of humans that will ever ex- ist is high. This objection, originally by Dennis Dieks (1992), is now known by Nick Bostrom’s name for it: the "Self-Indication Assumption From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Doomsday argument 6 objection". It can be shown that some SIAs prevent any inference of N from n (the cur- rent population); for details of this argument from the Bayesian inference perspective see: Self-Indication Assumption Doomsday argu- ment rebuttal. Many worlds John Eastmond’s "Many-Worlds Resolution of the Doomsday Argument" claims that when the Doomsday Argument is extended from a form that deals with a single historic timeline into one dealing with the many bifurcating simultaneous histories suggested by the many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics then one finds that the general- ized argument no longer makes any predic- tion about the future total size of the human species. More specifically, if each finite value of total population size is realized in a differ- ent future, then learning of our present posi- tion from the beginning of the human species does not change our prior belief about which particular total population size we will find ourselves experiencing in one of humanity’s many futures (assuming that versions of us live long enough to see versions of Doomsday). Caves’ rebuttal Caves’ Bayesian argument says that the uni- form distribution assumption is incompatible with the Copernican principle, not a con- sequence of it. He gives a number of examples to argue that Gott’s rule is implausible. For instance, he says, imagine stumbling into a birthday party, about which you know nothing: Your friendly enquiry about the age of the celebrant elicits the reply that she is celebrating her (tp = ) 50th birthday. According to Gott, you can predict with 95% confidence that the woman will survive between [50]/39 = 1.28 years and 39[×50] = 1,950 years into the future. Since the wide range encompasses reasonable expectations regarding the woman’s survival, it might not seem so bad, till one realizes that [Gott’s rule] predicts that with probability 1/2 the woman will survive beyond 100 years old and with probability 1/3 beyond 150. Few of us would want to bet on the woman’s survival using Gott’s rule. (See Caves’ online paper below.) Although this example exposes a weakness in J. Richard Gott’s "Copernicus method" DA (that he does not specify when the "Coperni- cus method" can be applied) it is not pre- cisely analogous with the modern DA; epi- stemological refinements of Gott’s argument by philosophers such as Nick Bostrom specify that: Knowing the absolute birth rank (n) must give no information on the total population (N). Careful DA variants specified with this rule aren’t shown implausible by Caves’ "Old Lady" example above, because, the woman’s age is given prior to the estimate of her lifespan. Since human age gives an estimate of survival time (via actuarial tables) Caves’ Birthday party age-estimate could not fall in- to the class of DA problems defined with this proviso. To produce a comparable "Birthday party example" of the carefully specified Bayesian DA we would need to completely exclude all prior knowledge of likely human life spans; in principle this could be done (e.g.: hypothetic- al Amnesia chamber). However, this would remove the modified example from everyday experience. To keep it in the everyday realm the lady’s age must be hidden prior to the survival estimate being made. (Although this is no longer exactly the DA, it is much more comparable to it.) Without knowing the lady’s age, the DA reasoning produces a rule to convert the birthday (n) into a maximum lifespan with 50% confidence (N). Gott’s Copernicus meth- od rule is simply: Prob (N < 2n) = 50%. How accurate would this estimate turn out to be? Western demographics are now fairly uni- form across ages, so a random birthday (n) could be (very roughly) approximated by a U(0,M] draw where M is the maximum lifespan in the census. In this ’flat’ model, everyone shares the same lifespan so N = M. If n happens to be less than (M)/2 then Gott’s 2n estimate of N will be under M, its true fig- ure. The other half of the time 2n underes- timates M, and in this case (the one Caves highlights in his example) the subject will die before the 2n estimate is reached. In this ’flat demographics’ model Gott’s 50% confidence figure is proven right 50% of the time. From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Doomsday argument 7 Self-referencing doomsday argu- ment rebuttal Some philosophers have been bold enough to suggest that only people who have contem- plated the Doomsday argument (DA) belong in the reference class ’human’. If that is the appropriate reference class, Carter defied his own prediction when he first described the argument (to the Royal Society). A member present could have argued thus: "Presently, only one person in the world understands the Doomsday argument, so by its own logic there is a 95% chance that it is a minor problem which will only ever interest twenty people, and I should ignore it." Jeff Dewynne and Professor Peter Landsberg suggested that this line of reasoning will cre- ate a paradox for the Doomsday argument: If a member did pass such a comment, it would indicate that they understood the DA sufficiently well that in fact 2 people could be considered to understand it, and thus there would a 95% chance that 40 people would ac- tually be interested. Also, of course, ignoring something because you only expect a small number of people to be interested in it is ex- tremely short sighted - if this approach were to be taken, nothing new would ever be ex- plored, if we assume no a priori knowledge of the nature of interest and attentional mechanisms. Additionally, it should be considered that because Carter did present and describe his argument, in which case the people to whom he explained it did contemplate the DA, as it was inevitable, the conclusion could then be drawn that in the moment of explanation Carter created the basis for his own prediction. Mathematics-free ex- planation by analogy Think of the human species like a car driver. We’ve had some bumps, but no catastrophes, and our car (Earth) is still road-worthy, but we want insurance. We ask the cosmic in- surer how much a millennium’s cover will be, but they haven’t dealt with humanity before. How should they work out the premium? The Doomsday Argument says that all they have to ask is how long we’ve been on the road (at least 40,000 years without an accident), they should calculate our insurance based on us having a 50% chance of having a fatal acci- dent inside another 40,000 years. Insurance companies try to attract drivers with long accident-free histories not because they necessarily drive more safely than newly qualified drivers, but for statistical reasons: They calculate that each driver looks for in- surance quotes every year, so that the time since the last accident is a random sample between accidents. The chance of being more than halfway through a random sample is half, and if they are more than half way between accidents then they are heading for an accident in less time than the time since their last. A driver who hasn’t had a scratch in 40 years will be quoted a very low premi- um for this reason, but you shouldn’t expect cheap insurance if you’ve only passed your test two hours ago (equivalent to the accident-free record of the human species in relation to 40 years of geological time.) Analogy to the estimated final score of a cricket batsman A random in-progress cricket test match is sampled for a single piece of information: the current batsman’s run tally so far. If the bats- man is dismissed (rather than declaring), what is the chance that he will end up with a score more than double his current total? A rough empirical result is that the chance is half (on average). The Doomsday argument (DA) is that even if we were completely ignorant of the game we could make the same prediction, or profit by offering a bet paying odds of 2-to-3 on the batsmen doubling his current score. Importantly, we can only offer the bet be- fore the current score is given (this is neces- sary because the absolute value of the cur- rent score would give a cricket expert a lot of information about the chance of that tally doubling). It is necessary to be ignorant of the absolute run tally before making the pre- diction because this is linked to the likely total, but if the likely total and absolute value are not linked the survival prediction can be made after discovering the batter’s current score. Analogously, the DA says that if the absolute number of humans born gives no in- formation on the number that will be, we can predict the species’ total number of births From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Doomsday argument 8 after discovering that 60 billion people have ever been born: with 50% confidence it is 120 billion people, so that there is better- chance-than-not that the last human birth will occur before the 23rd century. It is not true that the chance is half, whatever is the number of runs currently scored; batting records give an empirical cor- relation between reaching a given score (50 say) and reaching any other, higher score (say 100). On the average, the chance of doubling the current tally may be half, but the chance of reaching a century having scored fifty is much lower than reaching ten from five. Thus, the absolute value of the score gives information about the likely final total the batsman will reach, beyond the “scale invariant”.[9] An analogous Bayesian critique of the DA is that we somehow possess prior knowledge of the all-time human population distribution (total runs scored), and that this is more sig- nificant than the finding of a low number of births until now (a low current run count). There are two alternative methods of mak- ing uniform draws from the current score (n): 1. Put the runs actually scored by dismissed player in order, say 200, and randomly choose between these scoring increments by U(0, 200]. 2. Select a time randomly from the beginning of the match to the final dismissal. The second sampling-scheme will include those lengthy periods of a game where a dis- missed player is replaced, during which the ‘current batsman’ is preparing to take the field and has no runs. If we sample based on time-of-day rather than running-score we will often find that a new batsman has a score of zero when the total score that day was low, but we will rarely sample a zero if one bats- man stayed at the crease, piling on runs all day long. Therefore, the fact that we sample a non-zero score would tell us something about the likely final score that the current batsman will achieve. Choosing sampling method 2 rather than method 1 would give a different statistical link between current and final score: any non-zero score would imply that the batsman reached a high final total, especially if the time to replace batsman is very long. This is analogous to the SIA-DA-refutation that N’s distribution should include N = 0 states, which leads to the DA having reduced predictive power (in the extreme, no power to predict N from n at all). See also • Doomsday • Doomsday events • Fermi paradox • Final anthropic principle • Hypothetical disasters • Mediocrity principle • Quantum immortality • Simulated reality • Sic transit gloria mundi • Survival analysis • Survivalism • Technological singularity • Black swan theory References [1] Brandon Carter (1983). "The anthropic principle and its implications for biological evolution". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London A310: 347–363. doi:10.1098/ rsta.1983.0096. [2] J. Richard Gott, III (1993). "Implications of the Copernican principle for our future prospects". Nature 363: 315–319. doi:10.1038/363315a0. [3] Holger Bech Nielsen (1989). "Random dynamics and relations between the number of fermion generations and the fine structure constants". Acta Physica Polonica B20: 427–468. [4] The Doomsday argument formulation would still apply if humans developed unlimited lifespan. John Eastmond’s 2002 critique ([1]) concludes that "an infinite conscious lifetime is not possible, even in principle" because, he contends, that the DA’s uniform prior probability distribution applied over a countable infinity of observer-moments implies an uncountable number of the countably infinite bit-strings needed to specify each moment. [5] Doomsday argument two-case section is partially based on a refutation of the Doomsday Argument by Korb and Oliver. [6] The only probability density functions that must be specified a priori are: [1] Pr(N) - the ultimate number of people that will be born, assumed by J. From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Doomsday argument 9 Richard Gott to have a vague prior distribution, Pr(N) = k/N [2] Pr(n|N) - the chance of being born in any position based on a total population N - all DA forms assume the Copernican principle, making Pr(n|N) = 1/N From these two distributions, the Doomsday Argument proceeds to create a Bayesian inference on the distribution of N from n, through Bayes’ rule, which requires P(n); to produce this, integrate over all the possible values of N which might contain an individual born nth (that is, wherever N > n): This is why the marginal distribution of n and N are identical in the case of P(N) = k/N’ [7] See, for example, Introduction to Social Macrodynamicsby Andrey Korotayev et al. [8] The clock first appeared in 1949, and the date on which humanity gained the power to destroy itself is debatable, but to simplify the argument the numbers here are based on an assumption of fifty years. [9] The cricketing rationale for the lengthening of future survival time with current score is that batting is a test of skill that a high-scoring batsman has passed. Therefore, higher scores are correlated with better players who will then be more likely to continue scoring heavily. Historic batting records give a prior distribution that provides other useful data. In particular, we know the mean score across all players and matches. High and low posterior information (the current score) only gives a weak indication of the player’s skill, which is more strongly described by this prior mean. (This statistical phenomenon of informative averages is called Regression toward the mean.) • John Leslie, The End of the World: The Science and Ethics of Human Extinction, Routledge, 1998, ISBN 0-415-18447-9. • J. R. Gott III, Future Prospects Discussed, Nature, vol. 368, p. 108, 1994. • This argument plays a central role in Stephen Baxter’s science fiction book, Manifold: Time, Del Rey Books, 2000, ISBN 0-345-43076-X. External links • A non-mathematical, unpartisan introduction to the DA • A compelling lecture from the University of Colorado-Boulder • Nick Bostrom’s response to Korb and Oliver • Nick Bostrom’s summary version of the argument • Nick Bostrom’s annotated collection of references • Kopf, Krtouš & Page’s early (1994) refutation based on the SIA, which they called "Assumption 2". • The Doomsday Argument, Consciousness and Many Worlds by John Eastmond • The Doomsday argument and the number of possible observers by Ken Olum In 1993 J. Richard Gott used his "Copernicus method" to predict the lifetime of Broadway shows. One part of this paper uses the same reference class as an empirical counter-example to Gott’s method. • A Critique of the Doomsday Argument by Robin Hanson • A third route to the doomsday argument by Paul Franceschi • Chambers’ Ussherian Corollary Objection • Caves’ Bayesian critique of Gott’s argument. C. M. Caves, "Predicting future duration from present age: A critical assessment", Contemporary Physics 41, 143-153 (2000). • C.M. Caves, "Predicting future duration from present age: Revisiting a critical assessment of Gott’s rule. • "Infinitely Long Afterlives and the Doomsday Argument" by John Leslie shows that Leslie has recently modified his analysis and conclusion (Philosophy 83 (4) 2008 pp. 519–524): Abstract -- A recent book of mine defends three distinct varieties of immortality. One of them is an infinitely lengthy afterlife; however, any hopes of it might seem destroyed by something like Brandon Carter’s ‘doomsday argument’ against viewing ourselves as extremely early humans. The apparent difficulty might be overcome in From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Doomsday argument 10 two ways. First, if the world is non- deterministic then anything on the lines of the doomsday argument may prove unable to deliver a strongly pessimistic conclusion. Secondly, anything on those lines may break down when an infinite sequence of experiences is in question. • Mark Greenberg, "Apocalypse Not Just Now" in London Review of Books • Laster: A simple webpage applet giving the min & max survival times of anything with 50% and 95% confidence requiring only that you input how old it is. It is designed to use the same mathematics as J. Richard Gott’s form of the DA, and was programmed by sustainable development researcher Jerrad Pierce. Retrieved from "http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Doomsday_argument" Categories: Eschatology, Probability theory, Theories of history, Sociocultural evolution This page was last modified on 5 May 2009, at 20:32 (UTC). All text is available under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License. (See Copyrights for details.) Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a U.S. registered 501(c)(3) tax- deductible nonprofit charity. Privacy policy About Wikipedia Disclaimers From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Doomsday argument 11